Page images
PDF
EPUB

believe this doctrine, and the consequences will be salutary. The men who speak of the bad influence of believing moral necessity, are those who do not believe it. But what intelligent, good man ever believed it, without experiencing happy effects from it? We have all along heard it alleged that the doctrine has a bad tendency. But we have never discovered such a tendency. It has been lodged in the minds of multitudes of the wisest and best men. But they have all found its influence to be favorable to morality and piety. While those who declaim against it, and say that the belief of it has a pernicious effect, are those who do not believe it. It is my full conviction that the doctrine is the doctrine of the Bible, presented in a scientific form, and arrayed against hurtful errors; that it tends to honor God, to humble man, and to promote growth in grace, and that if we should embrace the antagonist doctrine, we should suffer loss.

One point more. The author of the Essay says: "According to the doctrine of free agency, the mind of man is endowed with a constitutional desire for happiness, which is the steady, abiding feeling of the mind, and is the mainspring of all the mental activity included in volition." Is this true? Do all our choices and voluntary actions proceed from self-love, or a desire for our own happiness? If so, then there is clearly a "uniform, invariable" connection of volition with an antecedent motive. And this “uniform, invariable antecedence" would, according to the author, involve the essence of fatalism; and the fatalism would be universal, leaving no place for free moral agency. For if “the desire for happiness is the mainspring of all the mental activity included in volition," that is, of all voluntary action; then all voluntary action stands in an invariable connection with one and the same antecedent motive, and, of course, excludes what the author calls free agency.

I am, however, far from admitting that self-love, or the desire of our own happiness, is "the mainspring" of all voluntary action. But I must content myself with a few brief observations on the subject.

[blocks in formation]

That self-love is not the spring of all voluntary action, is, I think, evident.

First, there are many principles and some of them very powerful principles in the human mind, which prove springs of that mental action which is involved in volition. Love of offspring, pity for the distressed, gratitude for favors, and other natural affections are as truly elements of our mental constitution, as the desire of our own happiness; and each one of them is as truly a spring of voluntary action, as self-love. How then can self-love be the spring of all voluntary action? We can say with truth, it is one of the springs of action. In all minds, it is a powerful spring. But is it therefore the only spring? In some minds it is the most powerful spring, the supreme motive, the motive, it may be, which governs almost exclusively. But because this is the case in some minds, can we conclude that it is so in all? Take the man, who loves God with all his heart and soul. Has he no spring of action above the desire of his own happiness? Is not his affection to God a motive distinct from self-love, and of a far higher and nobler nature? And do not those who maintain, that a desire for happiness is the spring of all voluntary action, manifestly overlook important principles, and attempt to simplify beyond nature, and in opposition to truth? They discover that self-love is a very powerful motive to action, and thence conclude that it is the only one. Others, who find gratitude to be a powerful motive to action might, with the same justice, conclude that this is the only motive. And others again, finding that pity for the distressed operates as a motive to exertion, might lose sight of everything else, and hold that all our actions result from pity.

As there are many motives of volition, besides self-love, so there are some motives which are of superior moral worth. Suppose you know that a man performs an action or makes a sacrifice from pure love to God, or to man, without the least reference in his thoughts or feelings to his own private good. Do you not at once pronounce it a deed of uncommon excellence? Even that benevolence which is mixed with other things, and of which we

can only say, that it has more influence than self-love, is regarded as a virtue. But that benevolence which is wholly disinterested, i. e., which does not proceed from any aim, direct or indirect, to promote our own gratification, is the object of universal admiration. And how many seek that admiration by appearing to be actuated by such benevolence, though really destitute of it.

It may perhaps be said, that while we are influenced by love to God or to man, we experience pleasure; and from this it may be inferred, that a desire for this pleasure is at bottom the mainspring of all moral action, and that all our other motives are to be resolved into this. But what is there in logic, or in experience, which can justify such an inference? The fact that we are pleased with the accomplishment of any object, as the honor of God, or the good of man, implies that we love that object antecedently to the pleasure we enjoy in it. Without the existence of such love to the object, how could the promotion of it give pleasure? The pleasure results from the preëxistent affection, and not the affection from a wish to obtain pleasure.

No one can doubt, that a desire for our own happiness is often the spring of our voluntary actions. But does it follow from this, that it is always so? How can that be considered as a motive to action, which is in no way contemplated by us which is not before the mind as an object of thought or desire, at the time of action? Look at a loving father, who, at the hazard of his own life, rushes into the water or the fire to rescue his little children. What moves him to do this? Is it a desire for his own gratification or pleasure? But he will tell you, he had no thought of this, and that he was urged on to do what he did, by the love and pity of his heart for his dear, suffering children. If he succeeded in preserving their life, he did indeed experience a high degree of pleasure, as a consequence. But to say that a desire for that pleasure was the motive of the parent's efforts, would be a contradiction to his own consciousness, and an abuse of language. And surely a devout Christian may, sometimes at least, be so influenced, so constrained, so borne on by love to Christ, that all thought of himself and all desire for his own gratification

will be excluded, and his fervent, holy love become the great and only motive of action. Facts of this kind certainly occur in the history of God's people. In how many instances are Christians, at the commencement of their course, and afterwards, conscious of loving God and rejoicing in his government, without any reference in their thoughts to their own interests, temporal or eternal? And is not such pure love to God, such a rising above private interest, and such annihilation of self generally regarded as among the clearest marks of holiness, and as what may be expected to exist in proportion to the measure of sanctification? The unregenerate are "lovers of themselves." They have no moral affection of a higher character than self-love. But can it be the same with those who bear the image of Christ? Is there no object in the universe which they love, except in subserviency to their own personal welfare? Is all duty performed by saints and angels from that one principle? To suppose this seems to me as unphilosophical and untrue, as to suppose that all the operations in the natural world are to be traced to the power of steam, or to electricity. True philosophy leads us to account for the phenomena in the natural world by a great variety of principles or laws, many of which are entirely distinct from each other. And why should it not lead us to do the same in the moral world, and to trace the actions of intelligent, moral beings, to all that variety of principles or motives, from which they evidently result? Why should we refuse to admit what is so manifest, that a variety of causes or springs of action as really exist and operate in the world of mind, as in the world of matter?

[ocr errors]

:

REPLY TO "INQUIRER."*

[ocr errors]

THE writer, whose questions and remarks I shall now consider, conceals his name, and calls himself "Inquirer. He doubtless has sufficient reasons for writing anonymously. But what weight is there in the reasons which he suggests in his "Apology?" He thinks he may be allowed to conceal his name, because he does not come forward as a teacher, but as a learner. But why is it less proper for one, who presents himself before the public as an "Inquirer" and learner, to make known his real name, than for one who presents himself as a teacher? It is certainly very honorable for a man to "take the attitude of a learner;" especially if, in that modest attitude, he manifests high intellectual attainments, and gives his readers reason to think that he is able to teach as well as to learn.

But I have no disposition to complain of "Inquirer," for not giving his name to the public. Nor will I evade the task of answering his inquiries because he writes anonymously. As the questions are important, I will seriously attend to them, without being anxious to know from whom they come. I am very willing to converse with persons behind the curtain, whose words I hear, but whose faces I have not the pleasure to see, on condition that they treat subjects with propriety, and show by their words, that they are worthy of respect, as the two anonymous writers do, with whom I am concerned in these discussions. After all, it must seem rather singular for me, in my own name, to be publicly discussing subjects with two writers, possessed of no ordinary powers of mind, but who conceal their names. I however make no objection. Still one in my case cannot be quite certain how the thing will end. If I should commit mistakes, or if I should be unsuc

* First published in the Am. Bib. Repos., 1840 and 1841, in reply to "Inquirer, ” April, 1840.

« PreviousContinue »